Comparison with 1872 |
|
group, the later and more highly perfected sub-groups, from branching out and seizing on many new places in the polity of Nature, will constantly tend to supplant and destroy the earlier and less improved sub-groups. Small and broken groups and sub-groups will finally
....... 1860 1861 1866 1869 1872 | tend to 1859 |
disappear. Looking to the future, we can predict that the groups of organic beings which are now large and triumphant, and which are least broken up, that is, which
have as yet have as yet 1872 |
as yet have 1859 1860 1861 1866 1869 |
suffered least extinction,
will, will, 1872 | will 1859 1860 1861 1866 1869 |
for a long
period, period, 1872 | period 1859 1860 1861 1866 1869 |
continue to increase. But which groups will ultimately prevail, no man can predict; for we
....... 1872 | well 1859 1860 1861 1866 1869 |
know that many groups, formerly most extensively developed, have now become extinct. Looking still more remotely to the future, we may predict that,
owing to the continued and steady increase of the larger groups, a multitude of smaller groups will become utterly extinct, and leave no modified descendants; and consequently
that, that, 1866 1869 1872 | that 1859 1860 1861 |
of the species living at any one period, extremely few will transmit descendants to a remote futurity. I shall have to return to this subject in the chapter on Classification, but I may add that
as, according to as, according to 1872 |
on 1859 1860 1861 1866 |
as according to 1869 |
this
view, view, 1872 | view 1859 1860 1861 1866 1869 |
....... 1869 1872 | of 1859 1860 1861 1866 |
extremely few of the more ancient species
have have 1869 1872 | having 1859 1860 1861 1866 |
transmitted
descendants descendants 1872 | descendants, 1859 1860 1861 1866 1869 |
to the present day, and, as to the present day, and, as 1872 |
and on the view of 1859 1860 1861 1866 |
and as 1869 |
all the descendants of the same species
form form 1869 1872 | making 1859 1860 1861 1866 |
a class, we can understand how it is that there
exists exists 1872 | exist 1859 1860 1861 1866 1869 |
so so 1869 1872 | but very 1859 1860 1861 1866 |
few classes in each main division of the animal and vegetable kingdoms. Although
....... 1869 1872 | extremely 1859 1860 1861 1866 |
few of the most ancient species
have left have left 1869 1872 |
may now have living and 1859 1860 |
now have living and 1861 1866 |
modified descendants,
yet, yet, 1866 1869 1872 | yet 1859 1860 1861 |
at
....... 1869 1872 | the most 1859 1860 1861 1866 |
remote geological
periods, periods, 1869 1872 | period, 1859 1860 1861 1866 |
the earth may have been
almost as almost as 1869 1872 | as 1859 1860 1861 1866 |
well peopled with
....... 1869 1872 | many 1859 1860 1861 1866 |
species of many genera, families, orders, and classes, as at the present
time. time. 1872 | day. 1859 1860 1861 1866 1869 |
|
On
the
degree
to
which
Organisation
tends
to
advance.
—
|
Natural selection
acts, as we have seen, exclusively
by the preservation and accumulation of variations, which are
beneficial under the organic and inorganic conditions of life
to which each creature is
at each successive period exposed.
The ultimate result will be
that each creature will
tend
to become more and more improved in relation to its
conditions
of life.
This improvement will, I think,
inevitably lead
to the gradual advancement of the organisation of the greater number of living beings throughout the world. But here we enter on a very intricate subject, for naturalists have not defined to each other's
satisfaction what is meant by an advance in organisation. Amongst the vertebrata the degree of intellect and an approach in structure to man clearly come into play. It might be thought that the amount of change which the various parts and organs undergo
in their development from the embryo to maturity would suffice as a standard of comparison; but there are cases, as with certain parasitic crustaceans, in which several parts of the structure become less perfect, so that the mature animal cannot be called higher than its larva. Von Baer's
standard seems the most widely applicable and the best, namely, the amount of differentiation of the different
parts (in
the adult state,
as I should be inclined to add)
and
their specialisation for different functions; or, as Milne Edwards would express it, the completeness of the division of physiological labour. But we shall see how obscure a
subject this
is if we look, for instance, to fish,
amongst which some naturalists rank those as highest which, like the sharks, approach nearest to reptiles;
whilst other naturalists rank the common bony or teleostean fishes as the highest, inasmuch as they are most strictly fish-like, and differ most from the other vertebrate classes. Still
more plainly we see
the obscurity of the subject by turning to plants, with
which the standard of intellect is of course quite excluded; and here some botanists rank those plants as highest which have every organ, as sepals, petals, stamens, and pistils, fully developed in each flower; whereas other botanists, probably with more truth, look at the plants which have their several organs much modified and somewhat
reduced in number as being of
the highest
rank.
|
|
If we look at the
differentiation and specialisation of the several organs of
each being when adult (and this will include the advancement of the brain for intellectual purposes)
as the best standard of highness of organisation,
natural selection clearly leads towards highness;
for all physiologists admit that the specialisation of organs, inasmuch as they perform in this state
their functions better, is an advantage to each being; and hence the accumulation of variations tending towards specialisation is within the scope of natural selection. On the other hand, we can see, bearing in mind that all organic beings are striving to increase at a high ratio and to seize on every ill-occupied
place in the economy of nature, that it is quite possible for natural selection gradually to fit an organic
being to a situation in which several organs would be superfluous and
useless: in such cases there might
be retrogression in the scale of organisation. Whether organisation on the whole has actually advanced from the remotest geological periods to the present day will be more conveniently discussed in our chapter on Geological Succession. |
|
But it may be objected that if all organic beings thus tend to rise in the scale, how is it that throughout the world a multitude of the lowest forms still exist; and how is it that in each great class some forms are far more highly developed than others? Why have not the more highly developed forms everywhere supplanted and exterminated the lower? Lamarck, who believed in an innate and inevitable tendency towards perfection in all organic beings, seems to have felt this difficulty so strongly, that he was led to suppose that new and simple forms were
continually being produced by spontaneous generation. ↑1 blocks not present in 1859 1860 1869 1872; present in 1861 1866 | I need hardly say that Science in her present state does not countenance the belief that living creatures are now ever produced from inorganic matter.
|
Science
has not as yet proved the truth of this
belief, whatever the future may reveal. On my
theory the present
existence of lowly organised
productions
offers no difficulty; for natural selection
includes no necessary and universal law of advancement or
development— it only takes advantage of such variations as arise and are beneficial to each creature under its complex relations of life. And it may be asked what advantage, as far as we can see, would it be to an infusorian animalcule— to an intestinal worm— or even to an earth-worm, to be highly organised? If it were no advantage, these forms would be left
by natural selection
unimproved or but little improved;
and might remain for indefinite ages in their present little advanced
condition. And geology tells us that some of the lowest forms, as the infusoria and rhizopods, have remained for an enormous period in nearly their present state. But to suppose that most of the many now existing low forms have not in the least advanced since the first dawn of life would be rash;
for every naturalist who has dissected some of the beings now ranked as very low in the scale, must have been struck with their really wondrous and beautiful organisation. |
|
Nearly the same remarks are applicable if we look to the great existing differences in the
grades of organisation which occur within almost every
great group; for instance, to
the co-existence
of mammals and fish in the vertebrata,—
to the co-existence of man and the ornithorhynchus
amongst mammalia— or
of the shark and amphioxus,
which latter fish in the extreme simplicity of its structure closely
approaches the invertebrate classes. But mammals and fish hardly come into competition with each other; the advancement of certain mammals or of the whole class
to the highest grade of organisation
would not lead to their taking the place of, and thus exterminating,
fishes. Physiologists believe that the brain must be bathed by warm blood to be highly active, and this requires aërial
respiration; so that warm-blooded mammals when inhabiting the water live
under some
disadvantages
compared with fishes. In this latter class,
members of the shark family would not tend to supplant the lancelet; for the lancelet, as I hear from Fritz Müller,
has as sole companion and competitor on the barren sandy shore of South Brazil, an anomalous annelid. The three lowest orders of mammals, namely, marsupials, edentata, and rodents, co-exist in South America in the same region with numerous monkeys, and probably interfere little with each other. Although organisation, on the whole, may have advanced and be advancing
throughout the world, yet the scale will still
present all
degrees of perfection; for the high advancement of certain whole classes, or of certain members of each class, does not at all necessarily lead to the extinction of those groups with which they do not enter into close competition. In some cases, as we shall hereafter see, lowly organised forms seem
to have been preserved to the present day
from inhabiting peculiar
or isolated
stations, where they have been subjected to less severe competition, and where they have existed in
scanty numbers,
which, as already explained,
retards
the chance of favourable
variations arising. |
|
Finally, I believe that lowly
organised forms now exist in numbers
throughout the world, and in nearly every class,
from various causes. In some cases favourable variations
may never have arisen for natural selection
to act on and accumulate. In no case, probably, has time sufficed for the utmost possible amount of development. In some few cases there may have
been what we must call retrogression of organisation. But the main cause lies in the circumstance
that under very simple conditions of life a high organisation would be of no service,— possibly would be of actual disservice, as being of a more delicate nature, and more liable to be put out of order and thus
injured. |
|
A difficulty, diametrically opposite to this which we have just been considering, has been advanced, namely,
looking
to the dawn
of life, when all organic beings, as we may imagine,
presented the simplest structure, how
could
the first steps in advancement or in the differentiation and specialisation
of parts have arisen?
Mr. Herbert Spencer would probably answer that
as soon as the most
simple unicellular organism came by growth or division to be compounded of several cells, or became attached to any supporting surface, his law would come into action, namely,
"that homologous units of any order become differentiated in proportion as their relations to incident forces become different." But as we have no facts to guide us, all
speculation on the subject is useless. It is, however, an error to suppose that there would be no struggle for existence, and, consequently, no natural selection, until many forms had been produced: variations in a single species inhabiting an isolated station might be beneficial, and
through their preservation either
the whole mass of individuals might become
modified, or two distinct forms might arise. But
I must recur to what was stated
towards the close of the Introduction, where I say that
no one ought to feel surprise at much remaining as yet unexplained on the origin of species, if due allowance be made
for our profound ignorance on the mutual relations of the inhabitants of the world during
the many past epochs in its history.
↑Subtitle not present 1859 1860 1861 1872 |
Various
Objections
considered.
1866 1869 |
|
I need allude only to two other objections: a distinguished botanist,
Mr. H. C. Watson,
believes
that I have overrated the importance of divergence of character (in which, however, he apparently believes), and that convergence
of character,
as it may be called, has likewise played a part.
I will only remark that if
two species
of two
allied genera, both
produced a number
of new and divergent species, I can believe that they might sometimes
approach each other so closely that they would for convenience sake
be classed in
the same new
genus,
and thus two
genera would converge into one;
but from the strength of the principle of inheritance, and from the two parent-species already differing and consequently tending to vary in a somewhat different manner, it seems hardly credible that the two new groups would not at least form distinct sections in the genus.
But it would in most cases be extremely rash to attribute to convergence a close and general similarity of structure in the modified descendants of widely distinct forms. The shape of a crystal is determined solely by the molecular forces, and it is not surprising that dissimilar substances should sometimes assume the same form; but with organic beings we should bear in mind that the form of each depends on an infinitude of complex relations, namely on the variations which have arisen, these being due to causes far too intricate to be followed out,— on the nature of the variations which have been preserved or selected, and this depends on the surrounding physical conditions, and in a still higher degree on the surrounding organisms with which each being has come into competition,— and lastly, on inheritance (in itself a fluctuating element) from innumerable progenitors, all of which have had their forms determined through equally complex relations. It is incredible that the descendants of two organisms, which had originally differed in a marked manner, should ever afterwards converge so closely as to lead to a near approach to identity throughout their whole organisation. If this had occurred, we should meet with the same form, independently of genetic connection, recurring in widely separated geological formations; and the balance of evidence is opposed to any such an admission. |
|
Mr. Watson has also objected that the continued action of natural selection
with
divergence of character
will
tend to make an indefinite number of specific forms. As far as mere inorganic conditions are concerned, it seems probable that a sufficient number of species would soon become adapted to all considerable diversities of heat, moisture, &c.; but I fully admit that the mutual relations of organic beings are more important; and as the number of species in any
country
goes on increasing, the organic conditions of life will
become more and more complex. Consequently there seems at first sight to be
no limit to the amount of profitable diversification of structure, and therefore no limit to the number of species which might be produced. We do not know that even the most prolific area is fully stocked with specific forms: at the Cape of Good Hope and in Australia, which support such an astonishing number of species, many European plants have become naturalised. But geology shows us, at least within the whole immense
tertiary period,
that
the number of species of shells, and,
probably,
of mammals, has not greatly or at all increased. What then checks an indefinite increase in the number of species? The amount of life (I do not mean the number of specific forms) supported on any
area must have a limit, depending so largely as it does on physical conditions:
therefore, if an area be inhabited by very many species, each or nearly each species will be represented by few individuals; and such species will be liable to extermination from accidental fluctuations in the nature of the seasons or in the number of their enemies. The process of extermination in these
cases will
be rapid, whereas the production of new species will
always be slow.
Imagine the extreme case of as many species as individuals in England, and the first severe winter or very dry summer would exterminate thousands on thousands of species. Rare species, and each species will become rare if the number of species become in any country
indefinitely increased, will, on the principle often explained, present within a given period few favourable
variations; consequently, the process of giving birth to new specific forms will
thus be retarded. When any species becomes very rare, close interbreeding will help in
exterminating
it; at least
authors have thought that this comes into play in accounting for the deterioration of Aurochs
in Lithuania, of Red Deer in Scotland, and of Bears
in Norway, &C.
As far as animals are concerned, some species are closely adapted to prey on some one other being; but if this other being had been rare, it would not have been any advantage to the animal to have been produced in close relation to its prey: therefore, it would not have been produced by natural selection.
Lastly, and this I am inclined to think is the most important element, a dominant species, which has already beaten many competitors in its own home, will tend to spread and supplant many others. Alph. de Candolle has shown that those species which spread widely
tend generally to spread
very
widely; and, consequently, they will tend to
exterminate
several species in several areas, and thus check the inordinate increase of specific forms throughout the world. Dr. Hooker has recently shown that in the S. E.
corner of Australia, where, apparently, there are many invaders from different quarters of the world,
the endemic Australian species have been greatly reduced in number. How much weight to attribute to these several considerations I do
not pretend to assign;
but conjointly they must limit in each country the tendency to an indefinite augmentation of specific forms. |
Summary
Summary
1866 1869 1872 |
Summary
1859 1860 1861 |
of
of
1866 1869 1872 |
of
1859 1860 1861 |
Chapter.
Chapter.
1866 1869 1872 |
Chapter
.—
1859 1860 |
Chapter.
—
1861 |
|
If
under changing under changing 1869 1872 |
during the long course of ages and under varying 1859 1860 1861 1866 |
conditions of
life life 1869 1872 | life, 1859 1860 1861 1866 |
organic beings
|